Richard Stanley
Well-Known Member
The following below is a fully excerpted book review in The Economist about a book, Why Liberalism Failed, authored by a professor of politics, Patrick Deenan, at the Jesuit's University of Notre Dame. The writer of the review correctly takes issue with Deneen's overwrought thesis. A thesis which seems to be profitably filled with typical Catholic tropes, and ... which coincidentally(?) aligns with the typological and Futurist cyclical theme of the Return of the (Salvic) King such as I discuss on Postflaviana.
After all, both Caesar Augustus and later imperial avatar, Jesus Christ, were savior kings, Princes of Peace and all. Those cheeky Republican Romans did not want a king, but they soon got Julius Caesar's adopted son, Augustus as an emperor, of the then new Novus Ordum Seclorum. That New Order delivered on the promise (of order) via the implementation of a feudal monarchy system that finally (mostly) ceded to the Liberalism discussed in the review. It mostly ceded to 'modern' Liberalism, except for a remnant of romantic Traditionalists that is. A fifth column of paranoid, yet powerful, snowflakes IMHO.
The reviewer also touches on the two broad streams that Liberalism has become today, addressing it somewhat differently than Jerry and I did in our Cultural Degradation blog post. The reviewer closes by making a parallel argument to the highly related debate between Religion and Science, in that (proper) Science is a process that demands questioning and internal debate, just as the otherwise anarchic 'freedom' unleashed by economic and social Liberalism demands responsible regulating mechanisms sans a King. And we must also be forced to presuppose that a King and his Church have good intentions and can indeed channel their god, or want to, in the course of regulating humanity.
Somebody's Leviathan must get gored, either the King's, or Liberal Democracy's, or ... the Anarchist's Randy Leviathan.
The reviewer correctly argues that Deenan's argument should be reframed, and I add that we should be alert that Liberalism's current low state may not be completely of its own doing. If the oldest institution in the West is wanting and expecting its King to Return, then is its Liberal enemy suffering merely at its own hands or the witting and unwitting paranoid agents of the King?
Apparently Professor Deenan didn't get the Traditionalist Catholic fake news messaging that Jesuits are Liberal degraders of the Divine Order.
There is a season for all things. The Romans, and King Jesus, gave the West the feudal system ordained by Joseph and the Pharaoh from Genesis 47. Control both sides against the middle.
The review begins:
Perhaps, Professor Deenan is not giving us the full story about why we now have a "meritocratic aristocracy", such as why higher education is comparatively so expensive today, or why Democracy is degenerating into a theatre of the absurd. Not that things were perfect before, but following the ecumenical movement and the Kennedy assassinations the Jesuit lead Catholics in the USA have taken charge of the three constitutional branches of governance, including the White House staff (excluding the Goldman Sachs contingent that is).
Mr Deneen uses the term “liberalism” in its philosophical rather than its popular sense. He is describing the great tradition of political theory that is commonly traced to Thomas Hobbes and John Locke rather than the set of vaguely leftish attitudes that Americans now associate with the word. But this is no work of philosophical cud-chewing. Most political theorists argue that liberalism has divided into two independent streams: classical liberalism, which celebrates the free market, and left-liberalism which celebrates civil rights. For Mr Deneen they have an underlying unity. Most political observers think that the debate about the state of liberalism has nothing to do with them. Mr Deneen argues that liberalism is a ruling philosophy, dictating everything from court decisions to corporate behaviour. Theory is practice.
The underlying unity lies in individual self-expression. Both classical and left liberals conceive of humans as rights-bearing individuals who should be given as much space as possible to fulfil their dreams. The aim of government is to secure rights. The legitimacy of the system is based on a shared belief in a “social contract” between consenting adults. But this produces a paradox. Because the liberal spirit mechanically destroys inherited customs and local traditions, sometimes in the name of market efficiency and sometimes in the name of individual rights, it creates more room for the expansion of the state, as marketmaker and law-enforcer. The perfect expression of modern liberalism is provided by the frontispiece of Hobbes’s “Leviathan” (detail pictured), with its sketch of thousands of atomised individuals confronted by an all-powerful sovereign.
Mr Deneen makes his case well, though he sometimes mistakes repetition for persuasion. He reminds the reader that, before the advent of modern liberalism, philosophers identified liberty with self-mastery rather than self-expression, with the conquest of hedonistic desires rather than their indulgence. He does an impressive job of capturing the current mood of disillusionment, echoing left-wing complaints about rampant commercialism, right-wing complaints about narcissistic and bullying students, and general worries about atomisation and selfishness. But when he concludes that all this adds up to a failure of liberalism, is his argument convincing?
His book has two fatal flaws. The first lies in his definition of liberalism. J.H. Hexter, an American academic, believed his fellow historians could be divided into two camps: “splitters” (who were forever making distinctions) and “lumpers” (who make sweeping generalisations by lumping things together). Mr Deneen is an extreme lumper. He argues that the essence of liberalism lies in freeing individuals from constraints.
In fact, liberalism contains a wide range of intellectual traditions which provide different answers to the question of how to trade off the relative claims of rights and responsibilities, individual expression and social ties. Even classical liberals who were most insistent on removing constraints on individual freedom agonised about atomisation. The mid-Victorians were great institution-builders, creating everything from voluntary organisations to joint-stock companies (“little republics” in the phrase of Robert Lowe, a 19th-century British statesman) that were designed to fill the space between the state and society. Later liberals experimented with a range of ideas from devolving power from the centre to creating national education systems.
Mr Deneen’s fixation on the essence of liberalism leads to the second big problem of his book: his failure to recognise liberalism’s ability to reform itself and address its internal problems. The late 19th century saw America suffering from many of the problems that are reappearing today, including the creation of a business aristocracy, the rise of vast companies, the corruption of politics and the sense that society was dividing into winners and losers. But a wide variety of reformers, working within the liberal tradition, tackled these problems head on. Theodore Roosevelt took on the trusts. Progressives cleaned up government corruption. University reformers modernised academic syllabuses and built ladders of opportunity. Rather than dying, liberalism reformed itself.
Mr Deneen is right to point out that the record of liberalism in recent years has been dismal. He is also right to assert that the world has much to learn from the premodern notions of liberty as self-mastery and self-denial. The biggest enemy of liberalism is not so much atomisation but old-fashioned greed, as members of the Davos elite pile their plates ever higher with perks and share options. But he is wrong to argue that the only way for people to liberate themselves from the contradictions of liberalism is “liberation from liberalism itself”. The best way to read “Why Liberalism Failed” is not as a funeral oration but as a call to action: up your game, or else.
After all, both Caesar Augustus and later imperial avatar, Jesus Christ, were savior kings, Princes of Peace and all. Those cheeky Republican Romans did not want a king, but they soon got Julius Caesar's adopted son, Augustus as an emperor, of the then new Novus Ordum Seclorum. That New Order delivered on the promise (of order) via the implementation of a feudal monarchy system that finally (mostly) ceded to the Liberalism discussed in the review. It mostly ceded to 'modern' Liberalism, except for a remnant of romantic Traditionalists that is. A fifth column of paranoid, yet powerful, snowflakes IMHO.
The reviewer also touches on the two broad streams that Liberalism has become today, addressing it somewhat differently than Jerry and I did in our Cultural Degradation blog post. The reviewer closes by making a parallel argument to the highly related debate between Religion and Science, in that (proper) Science is a process that demands questioning and internal debate, just as the otherwise anarchic 'freedom' unleashed by economic and social Liberalism demands responsible regulating mechanisms sans a King. And we must also be forced to presuppose that a King and his Church have good intentions and can indeed channel their god, or want to, in the course of regulating humanity.
Somebody's Leviathan must get gored, either the King's, or Liberal Democracy's, or ... the Anarchist's Randy Leviathan.
The reviewer correctly argues that Deenan's argument should be reframed, and I add that we should be alert that Liberalism's current low state may not be completely of its own doing. If the oldest institution in the West is wanting and expecting its King to Return, then is its Liberal enemy suffering merely at its own hands or the witting and unwitting paranoid agents of the King?
Apparently Professor Deenan didn't get the Traditionalist Catholic fake news messaging that Jesuits are Liberal degraders of the Divine Order.
There is a season for all things. The Romans, and King Jesus, gave the West the feudal system ordained by Joseph and the Pharaoh from Genesis 47. Control both sides against the middle.
The review begins:
OVER the past four centuries liberalism has been so successful that it has driven all its opponents off the battlefield. Now it is disintegrating, destroyed by a mix of hubris and internal contradictions, according to Patrick Deneen, a professor of politics at the University of Notre Dame.
The gathering wreckage of liberalism’s twilight years can be seen all around, especially in America, Mr Deneen’s main focus. The founding tenets of the faith have been shattered. Equality of opportunity has produced a new meritocratic aristocracy that has all the aloofness of the old aristocracy with none of its sense of noblesse oblige. Democracy has degenerated into a theatre of the absurd. And technological advances are reducing ever more areas of work into meaningless drudgery. “The gap between liberalism’s claims about itself and the lived reality of the citizenry” is now so wide that “the lie can no longer be accepted,” Mr Deneen writes. What better proof of this than the vision of 1,000 private planes whisking their occupants to Davos to discuss the question of “creating a shared future in a fragmented world”?
The gathering wreckage of liberalism’s twilight years can be seen all around, especially in America, Mr Deneen’s main focus. The founding tenets of the faith have been shattered. Equality of opportunity has produced a new meritocratic aristocracy that has all the aloofness of the old aristocracy with none of its sense of noblesse oblige. Democracy has degenerated into a theatre of the absurd. And technological advances are reducing ever more areas of work into meaningless drudgery. “The gap between liberalism’s claims about itself and the lived reality of the citizenry” is now so wide that “the lie can no longer be accepted,” Mr Deneen writes. What better proof of this than the vision of 1,000 private planes whisking their occupants to Davos to discuss the question of “creating a shared future in a fragmented world”?
Perhaps, Professor Deenan is not giving us the full story about why we now have a "meritocratic aristocracy", such as why higher education is comparatively so expensive today, or why Democracy is degenerating into a theatre of the absurd. Not that things were perfect before, but following the ecumenical movement and the Kennedy assassinations the Jesuit lead Catholics in the USA have taken charge of the three constitutional branches of governance, including the White House staff (excluding the Goldman Sachs contingent that is).
Mr Deneen uses the term “liberalism” in its philosophical rather than its popular sense. He is describing the great tradition of political theory that is commonly traced to Thomas Hobbes and John Locke rather than the set of vaguely leftish attitudes that Americans now associate with the word. But this is no work of philosophical cud-chewing. Most political theorists argue that liberalism has divided into two independent streams: classical liberalism, which celebrates the free market, and left-liberalism which celebrates civil rights. For Mr Deneen they have an underlying unity. Most political observers think that the debate about the state of liberalism has nothing to do with them. Mr Deneen argues that liberalism is a ruling philosophy, dictating everything from court decisions to corporate behaviour. Theory is practice.
The underlying unity lies in individual self-expression. Both classical and left liberals conceive of humans as rights-bearing individuals who should be given as much space as possible to fulfil their dreams. The aim of government is to secure rights. The legitimacy of the system is based on a shared belief in a “social contract” between consenting adults. But this produces a paradox. Because the liberal spirit mechanically destroys inherited customs and local traditions, sometimes in the name of market efficiency and sometimes in the name of individual rights, it creates more room for the expansion of the state, as marketmaker and law-enforcer. The perfect expression of modern liberalism is provided by the frontispiece of Hobbes’s “Leviathan” (detail pictured), with its sketch of thousands of atomised individuals confronted by an all-powerful sovereign.

Mr Deneen makes his case well, though he sometimes mistakes repetition for persuasion. He reminds the reader that, before the advent of modern liberalism, philosophers identified liberty with self-mastery rather than self-expression, with the conquest of hedonistic desires rather than their indulgence. He does an impressive job of capturing the current mood of disillusionment, echoing left-wing complaints about rampant commercialism, right-wing complaints about narcissistic and bullying students, and general worries about atomisation and selfishness. But when he concludes that all this adds up to a failure of liberalism, is his argument convincing?
His book has two fatal flaws. The first lies in his definition of liberalism. J.H. Hexter, an American academic, believed his fellow historians could be divided into two camps: “splitters” (who were forever making distinctions) and “lumpers” (who make sweeping generalisations by lumping things together). Mr Deneen is an extreme lumper. He argues that the essence of liberalism lies in freeing individuals from constraints.
In fact, liberalism contains a wide range of intellectual traditions which provide different answers to the question of how to trade off the relative claims of rights and responsibilities, individual expression and social ties. Even classical liberals who were most insistent on removing constraints on individual freedom agonised about atomisation. The mid-Victorians were great institution-builders, creating everything from voluntary organisations to joint-stock companies (“little republics” in the phrase of Robert Lowe, a 19th-century British statesman) that were designed to fill the space between the state and society. Later liberals experimented with a range of ideas from devolving power from the centre to creating national education systems.
Mr Deneen’s fixation on the essence of liberalism leads to the second big problem of his book: his failure to recognise liberalism’s ability to reform itself and address its internal problems. The late 19th century saw America suffering from many of the problems that are reappearing today, including the creation of a business aristocracy, the rise of vast companies, the corruption of politics and the sense that society was dividing into winners and losers. But a wide variety of reformers, working within the liberal tradition, tackled these problems head on. Theodore Roosevelt took on the trusts. Progressives cleaned up government corruption. University reformers modernised academic syllabuses and built ladders of opportunity. Rather than dying, liberalism reformed itself.
Mr Deneen is right to point out that the record of liberalism in recent years has been dismal. He is also right to assert that the world has much to learn from the premodern notions of liberty as self-mastery and self-denial. The biggest enemy of liberalism is not so much atomisation but old-fashioned greed, as members of the Davos elite pile their plates ever higher with perks and share options. But he is wrong to argue that the only way for people to liberate themselves from the contradictions of liberalism is “liberation from liberalism itself”. The best way to read “Why Liberalism Failed” is not as a funeral oration but as a call to action: up your game, or else.